|
IBRI Research Report No. 7 (1981)
THE APOLOGETICS OF FRANCIS SCHAEFFER
David P. Hoover
Covenant College
Lookout Mountain, Tennessee
Copyright © 1981 by David P. Hoover. All rights
reserved.
EDITOR'S NOTE
Although the author is in agreement with the doctrinal statement of IBRI, it does not follow that all of the viewpoints espoused in this paper represent official positions of IBRI. Since one of the purposes of the IBRI report series is to serve as a preprint forum, it is possible that the author has revised some aspects of this work since it was first written. |
ISBN 0-944788-07-6
INTRODUCTION
In the past eight years the name
Francis
Schaeffer has become a household word among a great many evangelicals.
Even within professional academia he has attracted considerable
attention
as he has spoken to large -- often overflowing -- university and
seminary
audiences across the country. That Schaeffer has had an impact upon a
wide
spectrnm of Americans there can be no doubt, but why such an
enthusiastic
reception? It surely cannot be the mere fact that he has added several
new volumes to an already inflated apologetic literature. Prior to the
appearance of his first two books in 1968,1 there were
plenty
of works in Christian apologetics -- these latter marking off two
rather
entrenched apologetic traditions.2
It seems to me that there are basically
two reasons for the response Schaeffer has gotten. First, in the words
of Richard Russell, "Francis Schaeffer is a pastor with a rare and deep
sensitivity to the spiritual plight of the present generation..."3
In Schaeffer, this sensitivity is coupled with a charisma that both
engages
and excites the minds of his audiences and readers. But there is this
and
more. Schaeffer genuinely loves those he confronts. This is admittedly
a personal and subjective judgment, but I believe it is true. I have on
several occasions witnessed Schaeffer, tired and spent after an hour's
lecture -- perhaps the third such lecture in a single day, taking an
additional
hour or two talking and witnessing to a cluster of young people
gathered
around him. This is the Schaeffer that best accounts for the L'Abri
phenomenon.
Secondly, there is Schaeffer's apologetic
approach. In the following section I will mention a positive and a
negative aspect to this approach, but suffice it to say here that
Schaeffer
does not have a "textbook" style. As he often has said, he is
interested
in giving honest answers to honest questions. Moreover, he restricts
questions
and answers to the truth-claims and intellectual defensibility of the
Christian
faith -- the question or comment that exploits the situation by
feeding,
in its effect, apologetic infighting is characteristically put off.
And,
whether in a popular lecture or any of his books, his style is a
rustic,
almost thinking-out-loud affair; yet it is just this quality at the
personal
level that proves to be so winsome.4
There is, of course, a great deal more
to Schaeffer's approach than what can be judged on the personal level
--
but it is very likely true that many young people come under his spell
for little more than this! In what follows we will be trying to assess
the merit or lack of merit in Schaeffer's apologetic as such. We will
not
be concerned with Schaeffer the theologian or Schaeffer the preacher --
except as it bears on the apologetic issue.
Some additional remarks before
proceeding:
in the section to follow, our main objective will be to appreciate what
is distinctive about Schaeffer's approach to apologetics. We will be
concerned,
so to speak, to get the big picture. After a brief flyover, I want to
turn
to some preliminary definitions and distinctions that will serve us in
a selective but critical assessment on foot. Then will follow a
response
to Schaeffer's critics, with discussion limited to Richard Russell's
charge
of rationalism and Cornelius Van Til's recent syllabus. The last
section
will give several criticisms of my own.
SCHAEFFER'S APOLOGETIC APPROACH
In considering Schaeffer's apologetics
it seems best to speak of an "approach" rather than a "system," because
for all that Schaeffer has written he claims not to have a technical
"philosophical
apologetic." That is to say, he does not have an apologetic system,
although
in He Is There and He Is Not Silent (1972) he seems, at least,
to
have attempted one. In any case, on page four of that work, Schaeffer
distinguishes
two senses of the term "philosophy": in the first sense philosophy is a
technical academic discipline, whereas in the second sense philosophy
is
dubbed the common man's "world view." I think there is a subtle (but
not
very serious) mistake here, but it will repay us to get clear on what
it
is.
Schaeffer wants to say that "all men
are
philosophers" in the sense that all men at least have a world view. But
it does not at all follow that one is a philosopher, whoever he may be,
merely by having a world view. Perhaps we can make this clearer
by substituting the German
Weltanschauung for world view. Accordingly,
we agree with Schaeffer that, with the possible exception of idiots,
infants
and deranged persons, everyone has a Weltanschauung -- which is
to say that everyone has a conceptual grid that is historically and
culturally
conditioned through which he makes sense of the world in which he lives.
But a Weltanschauung, or world
view,
is characteristically the sort of thing a person is -- if at all --
only
dimly aware of. Ask the "man-on-the-street" what his world view is --
what
its doctrines are -- and you are likely to get a blank (if not
suspicious)
stare, unless, of course, you have chanced upon a philosopher in our
first
sense (or at least a reasonably well-educated and reflective
individual).
Press him further -- say, for a rational defense of his world view --
and
he may take you for a Jehovah's Witness and hurry on.
The point I want to press is that to
the
extent that one is able to take up the topic of his world view, he is a
philosopher in sense one; and to the extent that one cannot say
anything
intelligible about the Weltanschauung that he assuredly has, he
is not a philosopher at all. A world view is simply not the sort of
thing
that persons, although having them, normally adopt. We all have one
because
we are inevitably members of a cultural millieu. So it is false that
every
man is a philosopher. It is true, however, that Weltanschauungen
can be philosophically analyzed or diagnosed profitably for one's
apologetic
endeavor.
To return from our digression, it is
important
at the outset to understand why Schaeffer eschews apologetic
system-building.
While I do not find any explicit reasons in his writings, it would
probably
be safe to list the following three: (1) Schaeffer is not a
professionally-trained
philosopher and is therefore simply acknowledging his limitations in
that
field. (2) The very notion of a rough-and-ready system that can easily
(once one gets the hang of it) generate answers to any and all
objections
to Christianity smacks too much of pretense -- in fact, saying of
apologetics
that it is a system belies the very character of apologetics. If I am
correct
in ascribing this reasoning to Schaeffer, there is a cleansing insight
couched in it for contemporary apologetics -- namely, apologetics is
more
properly a task requiring certain diagnostic and logical skills than a
seminary outline to be memorized. This is not intended at all to slight
the use of outlines and other materials in seminary courses; it is just
to say that such learning as may result in this way ought to be geared
to the development of the requisite skills.
Moreover, apologetics taken naively to
be a system invites the false confidence that one is always sure to
have
an answer in advance of any question whatever. Often, it has seemed to
me, system-bound apologists lapse into a somewhat abstract, heady
soliloquy
that nearly always fails to hit the problem nail on the head. Specific
questions require specific answers. One who wields a system that is
abstract
enough to cover every contingency that can arise within apologetic
discourse
has a "tool" that is far too blunt to be effective. It seems strange
indeed
to say, in effect, "Never mind what is specifically bothering you; just
attend to my system and the trouble will disappear!"
And (3), probably foremost in
Schaeffer's
mind, is that historically, when apologetics has been taught as some
thinker's
system, the risk is run that the "system" and its author will encourage
a binding discipleship. The danger, then, is that the disciples will
treat
their "system" as a kind of privileged knowledge, a veritable
Apologetic
Gnosis! My own seminary experience was torn -- or perhaps a better word
is excited -- in three different directions in apologetics (but through
no fault of my instructor). In retrospect two of those three now seem
to
me to have been of the "Gnosis" variety, while the third has proven to
have been a good beginning for subsequent work. The point to be
stressed
is that whenever students become captivated by a "sure-fire"
all-encompassing
method (or "argument"!) the result is very frequently apologetic
infighting
and precious little confrontation with those in need and those who
oppose
the faith.
Negatively, then, Schaeffer is not out
to build a system in the narrow sense -- indeed, as was indicated
earlier,
it is a category mistake to think that Biblical apologetics can be a
system!
But it would be a mistake also to think that Schaeffer approaches
problems
helter-skelter. He fully intends that his material and lectures be
systematic
-- which is to say, logical. In defending the faith one will have
constant
recourse to his understanding of the system of doctrine taught in
Scripture
as well as whatever Christian philosophy he possesses, but the
essence
of apologetics is Biblically sound and culturally relevant argument.
And it is here that Schaeffer has made a truly significant contribution.
The positive aspect of Schaeffer's
approach
is that he revived a practicing and diagnostic apologetics. The God
Who Is There was explosive for a good many seminarians back in
1968.
It is tempting to say that we all became instant Schaefferians! Perhaps
we were for the moment -- but that has not been the long-term effect.
Properly
understood, Schaeffer's work simply does not lend itself to that sort
of
thing. Rather, Schaeffer showed us dramatically what it means to engage
in apologetics. It was Schaeffer's contention that Christianity -- its
Gospel -- must become culturally deep if it is to be a formative power
for our times. Thus for a great many students a dry-as-dust scholastic
apologetics gave way to a culturally aware, diagnostic apologetics. And
whatever shortcomings we will see in Schaeffer's books, his approach
filled a long-standing vacuum. Schaeffer sums it up best in the
foreword
to Escape from Reason:
Every generation of Christians has this
problem of learning how to speak meaningfully to its own age. It cannot
be solved without an understanding of the changing existential
situation
which it faces. If we are to communicate the Christian faith
effectively,
therefore, we must know and understand the thought-forms of our own
generation.
(p. 7)
APOLOGIA: METHODOLOGY, ARGUMENT, AND PROOF
We now turn our attention to the bare
rudiments
of any viable apologetic.5 The question is, what sort of
minimal
constraints are there for an apologetic argument to succeed? We have
already
noted that "the essence of apologetics is Biblically sound and
culturally
revelant argument." This statement must now be further unpacked for
some
implications that may not be obvious at the surface.
Bernard Ramm, for example, seems to
labor
within a confusion when he discusses "The Concept of System In
Apologetics"
in his very fine book, Varieties of Christian Apologetics
(1961).
After stating that "Christian apologetics is the strategy of
setting
forth the truthfulness of the Christian faith and its right to the
claim
of the knowledge of God"6 (emphasis mine), he goes on to
stress
that apologetics, of whatever variety, is a system -- i.e., that
apologetics
is the sort of thing that can be called a system. He then gives
two senses of the term "system," the first of which is "a very tightly
organized set of propositions which are carefully interrelated."7
But it is his second sense of "system" that Ramm feels is appropriately
applied to apologetics:
A system may mean an interpretation of
some subject matter which is guided by certain fundamental assumptions
with no attempt made rigorously to coordinate everything that is said.
Rather it means a cluster of axioms and assumptions which function as
guides
and directives for the discussions and thus serve to unify and
integrate
the discussions.8
Although there may be an attenuated
sense
in which Ramm is correct, it can be very misleading to think of
apologetics
as a system.9 What is critical for apologetics, and what
alone
is critical, is sound argument for whatever conclusion is at stake.
Apologetics
itself has to do with arguing for a system, but is not
itself
a system. Moreover, for any putative truth-claim that comes up for
apologetic
scrutiny, there may be any number of valid and sound arguments to
provide
support for it. What is crucial for any "variety" of apologetics,
therefore,
is whether or not that apologetic employs a sound logical structure.
Returning to Ramm, it can be conceded
that
there are varying ways that Christianity's truth-claims (system) have
been
argued, both conceptually and empirically, but methodologically (or
logically)
no argument, no matter what label it goes by, is worth its salt if it
is
incoherent. What counts in apologetics is sound argumentation --
period!
And this is easily seen in the fact that it is solely in virtue of an
argument's
(apologia's) logical structure that its conclusion can be forced in any
way.
The interesting consequence of this is
that I might seem to a friend to be an "evidentialist" today, a
"presuppositionalist"
tomorrow, and even a "fideist" the day following. Yet in no way has my
logic changed -- I have let my opponent's background (whether, say,
science
or the arts) and his particular interests and intellect determine how
the
discussion will go.
In this regard, it would be foolish to
fault Schaeffer for not saying enough about evidences. If there is
something
amiss about the bare bones of Schaeffer's method, it is not his
historico-philosophical
approach. Schaeffer's writings have come out of years of confronting,
and
witnessing to, a generation of young people who have sought him out on
that level. The relevant questions are, does Schaeffer speak the truth,
and is his argumentation sound and cogent? We proceed now to address
this
issue more directly.
We have dwelt at length on what I have
termed Schaeffer's approach; we come now to method. The term "approach"
has so far forth been the more generic term; for our purposes "method"
will have the narrower sense of logical structure -- "logical
structure"
is at least subsumed under the notion of method. So to borrow the
language
of Ramm's book (though perhaps in a way he would disapprove) there are
a variety of apologetic approaches, but each is viable or laudable only
insofar as it can logically yield the desired conclusion.
Apologetic
approaches, no matter how many (Ramm puts the number at ten or twelve),
are, after all, types of
argument. What matters, then, is that an
argument both square with Scripture and that it be valid, sound and
cogent.
If this is so, and it hardly seems it could be otherwise, the
traditional
schools "evidentialism" and "presuppositionalism" ought to bury the
hatchet
because they both get whatever clout they have in virtue of
their
logical
viability. So for the presuppositionalist to say there can be no good
inductive
argument is just a presuppositionalist sulk. Moreover, for the
evidentialist
to disdain a presuppositional (reductio ad absurdum) argument is
likewise a sulk. I speak rather abstractly here, however, for it will
be
seen later that Van Til is not a presuppositionalist in the foregoing
sense
-- his system collapses of its own weight; but more on this in the
proper
section.
What is by now becoming apparent, the
Achilles
Heel of apologetics is its logical structure -- its method, not its
label,
nor even whether it finds an exact precedent in Scripture. There are,
of
course, texts in Scripture that certainly do serve as argument
paradigms
(Isa 41:21-29; Lk 1:1-4; Jn 20:31; Acts 1:3; and 1 Cor 15:1-8, to name
a few), but such paradigms, so far as I can see, serve the contemporary
apologist more in indicating a much wider range of ways to shore
support
for Biblical authenticity. Negatively, they count decisively against
fellow
apologists who insist that one cannot argue by testing a model in terms
of data -- for example, that archeological and empirical evidence in
general
can be used. Certainly there can be no question about the legitimacy of
appealing to fulfilled prophecy as counting in favor of theistic
authenticity
for the Bible. But it would be a mistake to suppose that Scripture
functions
as a sort of logic text, exhausting the number of ways one can advance
arguments for its status as the infallible Word of God. There is indeed
a Biblical "mode" of defending Biblical truth-claims, but that mode is,
to put it crudely, just a lot of "horse-sense" within God-ordained
logical
limits.
Let us now attempt a rough and brief
characterization
of the logical structure of Schaeffer's apologetic. Again, it is very
important
to be clear on precisely the sort of question this is -- it is not to
ask
what approach he takes. That has been established. It is to ask how his
basic argumentation goes. What Schaeffer appears to be doing --
especially
in He Is There and He Is Not Silent -- is to begin implicitly
with
Christianity as a model (or hypothesis), a conceptual structure that
best
accounts for, and explains the greatest range of data within, one's
world
of experience. For example, that there exists something rather than
nothing
at all, that there is and always has been a moral dimension to Human
life,
and that one can know things, are all explained, and explained
well,
by the Biblical revelation. In fact, Schaeffer contends that one would
have total mystery in these areas were it not for the Biblical "model."
In a nutshell, that, I think, is the Schaefferian strategy and I
have
no real quarrel with it. However, as will be seen, these major
contentions
of Schaeffer are at best poorly argued, and at worst, not argued at
all.
He seems, in fact, time and again to give the illusion of argument by
the
mere (hoped-for) connotations of words and coinages -- banking, in
effect,
upon his reader's intuitions, say, about what a person is.
But another difficulty pervades
Schaeffer's
works. While I do not put Schaeffer in the same rather leaky
epistemological
boat with Cornelius Van Til, Schaeffer speaks as though he has
shown
that the Biblical answer is the "only" answer, not merely the best
answer,
but an answer enjoying the logical status of necessity. For instance,
he
says, "Let us notice again that this is not simply the best answer --
it
is the only answer;"10 and again, "... as in the area of
metaphysics,
we must understand that this is not simply the best answer -- it is the
only answer in morals for man in his dilemma."11 But
flipping
back a few pages disclosed no argument for these stupendous claims.
Schaeffer,
(as I fear is the case with Van Til) is merely recording a
determination
that the logical necessity of his conclusions is bona fide -- he has
certainly
not argued it. But I will deal more fully with arguing the logically
necessary
status of existential truth-claims in the next section.
Upon reflection, what I find here in Schaeffer, as with Van Til, is
the desire to demonstrate (by discursive argument) that one's
conclusion
is necessarily true -- not true as a matter of fact -- but true
in the sense that one could deny the conclusion only upon pain of
self-contradiction.
This is the status claimed for the conclusion of the Ontological
Argument:
the fool cannot deny that God exists without contradiction. Now
Schaeffer's
and Van Til's motivation is understandable enough. It would be ever so
nice to "prove" one's claims -- so let us
for a moment worry over this notion of proof, what it is and what it
isn't.
What is a proof? This is an
extremely
important question for apologetics -- especially so because at least
one
prominent apologist has exclaimed there is absolutely certain proof for
the existence of God and the truth of Christian theism."12
But
what might this proof be? It surely cannot be a proof in the strict
deductive
sense of a string of dummy letters (premisses) entailing some
conclusion
C. Nor can it be, it seems to me, a version of the Ontological Argument
(although Alvin Plantinga has recently given what he considers to be a
sound version of that argument!).13
The notion of proof is a formal one
(and,
so to say, sacred to contemporary logic!). What is involved is a set of
statements (the premisses) that bears a relation to another statement
(the
conclusion) such that if the premisses are true, the conclusion would
have
to be true as well. This is a truism of deductive logic. But can there
be a set of statements that are all true (actually, it isn't necessary
that they all be true) and that severally entail that God
exists?
Yes and no.
George I. Mavrodes in his little work Belief in God has given a very nice treatment to the problem of what it means to prove that God exists.14 In deductive logic, the matter is rather simple: e.g., "if A, then B" and it is the case that A, then B is sure to be the case as well. But when we substitute empirically-laden premisses for the dummy letters, quite another matter arises.
This is seen in that one can advance a
logically legitimate question about any empirical or
existential
proposition -- even if perniciously. What the apologist must do,
therefore,
is to proffer the least objectionable premisses that will get him where
he wants to go. Suppose, for example, that the following "dummy"
argument
contains all real existential and empirical propositions:
P1
P2
P3
.
.
.
Pn
____
C
Now suppose, so far as you are
concerned,
all the premisses (all the P's) in the argument are true. Your
listener,
however, sincerely finds that he can neither accept P2 nor Pn,
both of which are critical for the argument to go through. He isn't
being
pernicious; it just is not clear to him that the propositions in
question
are true. What then? Well, your listener will not feel constrained by
dint
of the force of your argument to accept its conclusion. The next move
must
be yours, so you say, "Okay, let us substitute for P2 and Pn
the propositions P'2 and P'n. Both are hospitable
to your conclusion and your listener finds them at least plausible. Of
course these substitute premisses might also prove objectionable, in
which
case you would have to substitute P"2 and P"n and
so on. We also notice that the argument has certain formal properties
of
a deductive argument but is itself a purely inductive argument.
The question therefore becomes, is there such a thing as inductive
proof?
The answer, officially at any rate, is no. Such argumentation may be
correct,
plausible, or probable as concerns the conclusion, but so long as the
conclusion
is logically corrigible, the argument can only be persuasive. But I do
think there is sense in the question, when does an argument become a
proof?
For we frequently speak as though an inductive set of premisses "proved"
something to us. For example, the testimony for the prosecution proved
beyond a reasonable doubt that the accused was guilty. So, if our
colloquial
and inductive notion of proof is approved, an argument
becomes a
proof when our listener sees the conclusion to follow from the
premisses
and is convinced of this. In our second sense of proof,
therefore,
proof is always "person-variable."15 That is to say,
in most of those instances where we are
attempting
to "prove" a thing to someone, such a proof will invariably have the
status
of being a proof for that someone. It may not suffice as a
proof
for a different individual simply because that individual may not be
acquainted
with those premisses that the former person was. And indeed, "proofs"
do
seem to be interesting only to the extent that they stand to increase
our
knowledge. But let us not lose sight of why the discussion of proof
came
up: Schaeffer, at least on some occasions, seems to imply that he (like
Van Til) has accomplished a proof in the incorrigible sense -- but not
only are the arguments absent, such an argument is an impossibility. It
seems to me, however, that when Schaeffer lapses into the sort of
statements
that were quoted, they are more homiletic and hortatory than an
incorrigible
finish to an argument.
SCHAEFFER AND HIS CRITICS: RICHARD RUSSELL AND CORNELIUS VAN TIL
Richard Russell
In a review article for the International Reformed Bulletin
(1970),
Richard Russell, instructor in philosophy at Trinity Christian College
(Palos
Heights, IL) , charges Schaeffer with rationalism and individualism. My
concern will be with just the former.
At the outset it should be stressed
that
Schaeffer is primarily concerned with the intellectual
defensibility
of the Christian faith and its truth. This in itself is
unobjectionable.
Russell, however, faults Schaeffer for his overall interpretation of
what
has happened in the history of philosophy. He quotes Schaeffer in Escape
from Reason (p. 92) a saying "... the Jewish and Biblical concept
of
truth is much closer to the Greek than the modern." Now I am as dubious
of this remark as Russell is, but I think Russell has not attended to
what
Schaeffer means in remarks like these. I am convinced that for
a
significant number of Schaeffer's statements, what Schaeffer says is
not
always what Schaeffer means. It is true that Schaeffer thinks of
"modern
modern man" as post-Hegelian, but to conclude from this that Schaeffer
wants to champion pre-Hegelian rationalism, as Russell contends, is
entirely
unwarranted. Schaeffer is concerned for an intuitively sound logic
wherein
A is not non-A. Schaeffer is concerned for the law of identity (A is A)
, the law of contradiction (A is not non-A) , and the law of excluded
middle
(either A, or non-A). Without these logical laws there could be no
intelligible
discourse.
However, it is not really certain that these laws suffered at the
hands
of Hegel. Hegel is ambiguous at this point, and at any rate, his
subsequent
influence had least to do with his logic! Rather it was Hegel's
notion of nature and the vicissitudes of human endeavor and thought as
one organic and ever-developing whole that played upon the minds of
Bradley,
the pragmatists, and Whitehead. So far from being post-Hegelian in
logic,
Schaeffer's modern modern man within the Anglo-American culture has the
legacy and continuing development of nearly a century of logic.
Philosophically,
this has been the century of logic from Frege's early work through
Russell,
Whitehead, and Wittgenstein!
What Schaeffer must attend to is just
what
aspects of contemporary thought can be attributed to Hegel's influence.
Further, it seems to me, from typical Schaeffer examples (which often
have
the distressing feature of little more than name-dropping) , he reads
the
Anglo-Canadian~American tradition through a heavy existential and
phenomenological
mist. The Anglo-American tradition has majored in logic, the philosophy
of language, and the philosophy of science. In all these, the
"Law
of Excluded Middle" is alive and well.
But perhaps Russell's point may be
taken
against Schaeffer in yet another way. In Escape from Reason we
are
given diagrams which sum up Schaeffer's diagnosis of modern man. I
think
there may not merely be a minor flaw in the argument of the book, but a
decisive one. Tracing western man's philosophical roots to the present
day, Schaeffer finds much to criticize in Aquinas, Kant and
Kierkegaard.
Each of these thinkers built, as it were, a two-storeyed house but with
no logical staircase to connect the upper with the lower storey. It is
instructive to see what, in each "house," characterizes the storeys.
For
Aquinas it was nature/grace; Aquinas did much to set human reason off
on
its autonomously merry way. Next is Kant, who gave up on grace
altogether,
and with his religion of moral freedom, built a house of
nature/freedom.
And last, apparently, is that house that Hegel and Kierkegaard built --
faith/rationality.
Now in each house notice that the lower
storey is the realm of what may be ascertained by autonomous reason.
The
lower storey is the domain of the particulars of nature as
discriminated
and assessed by man and his logic:
GRACE
FREEDOM
FAITH
________
__________
_____________
NATURE
NATURE
RATIONALITY
In the upper storey is the element of freedom and that which
provides
meaning and significance to the downstairs of particulars. But in none
of these houses is there a logical (or coherent) connection from one
floor
to the other; there is no staircase. Thus, regarding these
philosophers'
"houses" as symbols of their systematically worked-out woridviews,
Schaeffer's
point is that in none of them can universality (meaning) logically
relate
to particularity (items in one's world of experience). In this I
believe
Schaeffer's analyses are basically sound.
Over against the despair of these faulty worldviews Schaeffer holds
out the Christian position, the Christian "house." Scripture, Schaeffer
tells us, speaks of both the "upstairs and the downstairs."16
This addressing of both universals and particulars in the Bible assures
us of the unity that was lacking in the other views. But of course Kant
"spoke" of upstairs and downstairs too, to use Schaeffer's metaphor. So
did Aquinas. How is it that mere biblical reference to both
universality
and particularity secures a coherence unobtainable in the other views?
To see whether Schaeffer faces a
difficulty
here we must attempt to make Schaeffer's "upstairs" and "downstairs"
explicit.
It seems to me that the only candidates for these two "floors" within
Schaeffer's
biblical commitments are (1) God and His decrees -- the source of all
created
meaning , and (2) the particulars of created reality -- including man
and
his moral responsibility. On the one hand, Schaeffer, subscribing as he
does to the Westminster Confession of Faith, would have to put in the
upstairs
of the Christian house "God and His decrees." Quoting from the
Catechism,
question number seven, "The decrees of God are, his eternal purpose,
according
to the counsel of his will, whereby, for his own glory, he hath
foreordained
whatsoever comes to pass" (emphasis mine). Note that this is a
commitment
to complete determinism -- theistic and teleological in character, but
a thoroughgoing determinism just the same.
On the other hand, the particulars of
Schaeffer's
downstairs include man as significantly free, significantly
responsible,
not an automaton. So we are bidden to take up residence in an
apparently
split-level house wherein upstairs is a radical determination of all
things
and the downstairs is area of "unprogrammed man," to use Schaeffer's
expression.
We have then:
God and His Decrees
_________________
Created Particularity
But what does this construction invite Schaeffer's opponent to say?
I do not doubt what the Catechism says in the least, but for all that,
doesn't this situation pose for Schaeffer an equally formidable logical
problem to that which destroyed the other "houses"? It certainly seems
that if each "house" is assessed according to its logically apparent
features,
Schaeffer's "house" doesn't get a staircase either. That is to say,
there
can surely be no staircase in the requisite sense if there is no
current
human understanding of the logical steps between, say, divine
foreordination
of all things and human responsibility. Indeed, God has addressed both
areas in His Word, but their logical unity (or integration) is nowhere
rationally exhibited. Thus while we should like to appreciate real
value
in Schaeffer's point that God reveals to us in His Word that His plan
is
ultimately coherent, we must hasten to add that not only doesn't
Scripture
logically harmonize certain of its clear teachings (concerning, e.g.,
the
Trinity, the Incarnation, and God's absolute sovereignty vis-a-vis
man's
responsibility), man may be quite incapable of construing such material
as free from logical difficulty (cf. Isa 55:8-9; Deut 29:29).
But if this is right, and if Schaeffer invites a rationalistic
assessment
of Christianity's most fundamental claims, then the blow to Schaeffer's
central thesis in Escape From Reason is devastating! He has
left
mystery and finitude of perspective out of account at a very sensitive
point. In fact, any quickwitted antagonist could, with Schaeffer's own
logic, dismiss Schaeffer's entire effort. One may simply not fault
Kant,
let us say, for failing to harmonize universality and particularity
within
his system when no Christian thinker has ever logically
penetrated
the problematics of God's decrees and man's responsibility -- unless,
that
is, it can be shown that the latter problematics arise for quite
different
reasons than in the Kantian system. (Alvin Plantinga has recently
advanced
an ingenious way out, but he seems to have come precariously close to
Arminianism.)17
I conclude, then, that Russell's point
is well taken if he has this sort of thought in mind. If I am right,
Schaeffer's
whole program in both Escape From Reason and The God Who Is
There
is left in the lurch. While we should not want to "escape reason," it
is
equally clear that we should not allow the case for Christianity to
rest
upon the human ability to exhibit Christianity as a perspicuously
logically-harmonized
system.
Cornelius Van Til
Recently Professor Emeritus Cornelius Van Til has allowed a rather
lengthy
critique of Schaeffer to be printed and sold at the Westminster
Seminary
Bookstore. Although there are several well-taken criticisms of
Schaeffer's
approach, Van Til's central concern is that Schaeffer has taken up the
cudgels of a basically Butler-Paley apologetic and that, despite
certain
superficial similarities of language, Schaeffer is not a
presuppositionalist
but a veritable Arminian in apologetics! I shall maintain that, insofar
as Schaeffer has been charged with holding an apologetic method that
fails
because it is not true to Van Til's apologetic, Schaeffer need have no
qualms. Schaeffer is being judged in terms of an incoherent apologetic
framework! The charge I make is quite serious, but, I think,
demonstrably
true.
Let me preface my remarks by
acknowledging
a real debt of gratitude to Professor Van Til, both through a reading
of
his books (many of them given me by him) and through personal
acquaintance
with him, for the stimulus he has been to my own development.
I will now respond to what strikes me
as
fallacious about the very heart of Van Til's presuppositionalism. If
his
apologetic fails, as I think it does, it can hardly be used to critique
someone else's thought. I will contend that Van Til's method does not
give
way because of any empiricistic critique, but because its own
logical
strategy, as specified by Van Til, simply cannot yield the only type of
conclusion Van Til will accept. It must be one hundred per-cent or
nothing.
But as we shall see, Van Til, in effect, logically short-circuits his
own
line of argument.
Van Til calls his method "presuppositional." Its chief feature is
presupposing
the truth of Christianity as the system that integrates all factuality
and that accounts for life as it is actually lived. The objective is to
show or demonstrate to one's opponent that Christian theism (1) truly
does
this, and (the much more ambitious claim) (2) that Christianity alone
can do this. The question is, can presuppositional argumentation
accomplish
these objectives?
Let us first review why it is that Van
Til insists that his presuppositionalism is the only approach that does
not ultimately sacrifice the truth of Christianity. To begin with, all
facts (presumably statable states of affairs) in the universe are such
by virtue of creation and so are God-interpreted (i.e., ultimately
rational)
facts. Particularly important for Van Til is that there are no "brute"
facts (that is, uninterpreted and therefore non-integrated and
non-rational
facts). Therefore, in principle, according to Van Til, one cannot know
any particular fact without exhausting its integral relation with every
other fact in the universe. Without the principle that the universe is
a rational whole, he seems to argue, one is epistemologically cut
adrift
upon a sea of pure contingency. Although man, with only a finite
intellect,
cannot fathom the universal context for each particular fact, God can.
This being the case, the way is open for man -- particularly, if not
solely,
the Christian man -- to "think God's thoughts after God" and thus
"reinterpret"
what has already been interpreted by God. But whereas God knows
exhaustively
and therefore incorrigibly, man knows analogically (i.e., in some such
fashion as God knows). And insofar as man's 'kiowledge" might be aptly
described a reinterpretation, Van Til would say his knowledge is
"knowing
truly."
But this is all very obscure. First, how does one know when he has
"reinterpreted"
a part of God's knowledge -- say, about some aspect of created reality?
Van Til, at this point, would doubtless introduce an array of
postulates
that are formulable from biblical texts. If the statement purporting to
be factual is consistent and/or deducible from any of these postulates
(presuppositions) , one has rightly reinterpreted and can be said to
know
"truly."
But it is not at all the same whether a putative assertion sustains
a consistency or a deductive relationship to another statement. If
consistency
is the desideratum, one is faced with the paradox that several
empirical
(hypothetical) statements might be consistent with the same
postulate,
but only one of which could be true! Moreover, each consistent
statement
would count, pace Van Til, as a "reinterpretation."
If deducibility is the desideratum, one ends in total rationalism,
and
it seems clear that this is not what Van Til wants. I think here we
have
an inescapable dilemma given Van Til's notion of what may be called the
"integrality principle." All facts are so related such that partial
knowledge
entails, in principle at least, exhaustive knowledge. Clearly, one
needs
some omniscience principle to vouchsafe any human knowledge whatever.
For
Van Til, this principle is embodied and confirmed (in part) by God's
revelation,
the Bible. But here is a problem:
Revelation for Van Til is just that; in
the case of the Old and New Testaments it is God Himself who reveals
Himself.
It is the inscripturated "Word of God" and God is speaking. Moreover,
as
we find in Psalm 19:1, the heavens do not declare that God "probably"
exists,
nor do the Scriptures evidence the least bit of doubt as to the
verities
they assert. How then can a believing apologist argue to a dubitable
and
corrigible conclusion? Is this not tantamount to telling God His
revelation
is muddled? Van Til would insist that this is just what "evidential"
apologists
invariably do.
Van Til's response is that the
inscripturated
"Word of God" is God speaking, and since it is God who speaks, the
content
of the revelation is authoritative -- in fact, absolutely
authoritative.
If so, one does not apply external criteria of testing to such an
authority;
one can only obey or disobey. For Van Til, any external checking
principle
-- e.g., logical coherence or even the corroboration of Scripture by
such
disciplines as archeology, paleontology, or astronomy -- must
tacitly
deny the ultimacy of God's authority by assuming a more ultimate
verificatory
authority (human reason), in terms of which the very worth and
credibility
of God's Word is judged!
But there are at least two problems
that
Van Til has ignored: (1) authority -- as pertaining to a document --
presupposes
authenticity,
and authenticity is straightforwardly a pressing epistemological issue.
If some alleged "canonical" literature X or Y is offered to us as the
infallible
Word of God (say, the Book of Mormon, or the Koran), it is certainly
not
impertinent but highly necessary to inquire into its theistic
authenticity
before accepting it as binding. And this leads to: (2) there
do
happen to be several 'canonical" literatures competing for allegiance.
Does one fideistically (no questions asked) just imbibe one of these,
or
is there some adequate process of rational discrimination that can help
to weed out those that are bogus?
Let us now briefly go to the root
problem
of Van Til's presuppositionalism -- why in principle it is not
a
viable apologetic method. In his Defense of the Faith (p. 100)
,
Van Til states, "The Reformed apologist will frankly admit that his own
methodology presupposes the truth of Christian theism"
(emphasis
mine) Van Til is embarking upon what he feels is the only
uncompromising
apologetic, and it is well to notice the wording here; we shall revert
back to it later. What is important is the strategy, the logical
structure,
that Van Til sets up. In Defense of the Faith, as elsewhere,
the
strategy outlined in the various passages on method stresses that the
believer
will put himself on the assumptions (or presuppositions) of the
unbeliever
for the sake of argument, and demonstrate that on those assumptions
"the
facts are not facts and the laws are not laws." In effect, the believer
performs a Socratic elenchus upon the unbeliever's major
assumptions
-- that is to say, he refutes the unbeliever's position by showing it
to
be either incoherent or inadequate or both (cf. Phaedo 101d,
and
both Kenneth H. Sayre's Plato's Analytic Method, pp. 3-56 and
Richard
Robinson's Essays in Greek Philosophy, pp. 1-15).
What is of special interest is that
there
is a critical symmetry outlined in Van Til's method with
respect
to analyzing first the non-Christian's position and then the Christian
position. If the symmetry is maintained, Van Til's conclusion about the
necessary
truth of the Christian position cannot possibly follow. When you, the
believer,
assume the non-Christian's presuppositions for the sake of argument,
you
are assuming them as provisionally true to see what would happen, for
according
to Van Til:
We can begin reasoning with our
opponent
at any point in heaven or earth and may for
argument's sake present
Christian theism as one hypothesis among many [!], and may for
argument's
sake place ourselves upon the ground of our opponent in order to see
what
will happen.18
The symmetry, then, is this: in both
cases,
your opponent's case and your own, the provisional or hypothetical
character
of the opposing (both) sets of pre-suppositions is the same. Neither
has
the status in the argument of being true, only of being
provisionally
true for the sake of analysis.
Now let us revert back to Van Til's
earlier
statement about presupposing "the truth of Christian theism." Although
there is a clear sense in which it would be okay to use this wording,
the
fuller context of Van Til's methodology passages shows that he has
shifted
the logical ground on the opposition. He is not presupposing his own
presuppositions
as being true -- the word "as" being elliptical for "as though" -- he
is
rather changing the rules of the inquiry when it comes his turn to be
examined
-- in effect, fudging on the logical symmetry that originally
determined
the ground rules for discussion. The wording in Defense of the Faith
must be taken quite literally -- even letterally -- if we are to see
what
has taken place! An assymetry is introduced, as we can now see
in
retrospect, that is designed to mysteriously endow the Christian's
presuppositions
with the remarkable logical status of self-evident truth!
If indeed one sets up the process of
analysis
on the basis that systems X and Y are both
hypothetically
true, or what is the same thing, provisionally true for argument's
sake,
one must, upon pain of incoherence, strictly adhere to those ruiles.
Van
Til does not do this. This is extremely serious because at stake in
apologetics
is sound argumentation -- one either has or does not have an argument.
If Y is the conclusion of an argument, it is essential to see how that
argument goes. But, assuming Van Til has been successful in rebutting X
via a reductio ad absurdum, the up-till-now equally
hypothetical
Y (Christianity) , is suddenly regarded as factually
necessary,
not hypothetically or provisionally true as in the case of the hapless
system X!
Lest this critique should seem cavalier, perhaps unfair, in
suggesting
that Van Til has only pretended the initial strategy so clearly marked
off in the above quotation, consider a rather amazing statement that
Van
Til makes against Buswell:
The argument for the existence of God
and
for the truth of Christianity is objectively valid. We should not tone
down the validity of this argument to the probability level. The
argument
may be poorly stated, and may never be adequately stated. But in itself
the argument is perfectly sound.19
This is a remarkably confused statement
-- a conflation of the categories of logic and metaphysics. Van Til,
the
metaphysical banker, is guaranteeing his disciples that they have
plenty
of
epistemological credit -- in fact, they can hardly overdraw their
account!
Because one is assured (fideistically) of what metaphysically must be
the
case, it does not matter much how one argues for it.
This is an unfortunate position to hold
since it is so vulnerable. One hardly needs reminding that one can have
a perfectly valid argument whose conclusion is factually false.
Moreover,
it is just the adequacy of an argument's formulation that constitutes
its
soundness.
What Van Til really means to say is
that
God really does exist and that testimony to this fact, no
matter
how feeble, will never lack a corresponding reality. There seems to be
no attempt to distinguish "kerygma" from "apologia" (they are
distinguished
in Scripture, e.g., 1 Pet 3:15), and so the question remains, is there
anything to Van Til's kerygma? Answer: only if God exists.
Although a more rigorous logical
critique
of Van Til's method could be given, I think the above line of criticism
is both fair and decisive. It will hardly do, therefore, as a platform
to criticize Schaeffer.
AREAS OF WEAKNESS IN SCHAEFFER'S APOLOGETIC
Again I shall preface my remarks with
an
expression of thankfulness and deep admiration for Dr. Schaeffer. He
has
been mightily used by God as a missionary to thousands of young people
-- beginning with the L'Abri work and now continuing through his books
and lectures. The following criticisms have no other intent than to
suggest
wherein Schaeffer might be more effective. My examples will hopefully
appear
as constructive efforts to indicate general tendencies, not a
harassment.
Also, it is only the apologetic aspect of Schaeffer's work that will be
the focus.
Schaeffer's Diagnosis of the
Historical
Roots of Modern Thought
Perhaps due to a lack of specific footnoting, a reader canvassing
Schaeffer's
books may become uneasy when generalizations are made about Plato,
Aquinas,
Kant and contemporary thinkers. Two examples may serve to illustrate
this:
Schaeffer speaks of Plato's "gods" being too small to account for unity
in diversity.20 However, it is at least dubious that Plato
was
a polytheist and far more probable that he was an atheist. While it is
true that in the Timaeus a "Demiurge" is depicted as forming
the
world according to the Ideal or Exemplary Pattern, most commentators
take
this language to be a pedagogical device on Plato's part. It is quite
certain,
at any rate, that Plato felt no compunction to reckon with any "gods."
When speaking through Socrates in the Euthyphro, Plato seems to
mock the very notion of a quarreling semi-corporeal nest of gods on
Olympus.
But with Kant, Schaeffer's facility or lack of facility with the
history
of philosophy is far more critical for his major concerns. Schaeffer
states
that:
Kant's system broke upon the rock of
trying
to find a way to bring the phenomenal world of nature into relationship
with the noumenal world of universals.21
The fact is, however, Kant had no
proof,
within his system, that there even was a "noumenal" world of
things-in-themselves.
He merely argued its bare possibility, and in any case, such a world
would
not have served in Kant's system as the supplier of universals.
Knowledge
for Kant was restricted to what the human mind could rationalize
through
its pure forms of intuition and its several categories. One can know
only
phenomena; the thing-in-itself may or may not have the good fortune to
exist. The mind conceptually brings to the raw appearances (sensations)
its categories and thus particularity is unified within a
conceptualism.
It is just false that the "noumenal" was even hoped to supply
universals
because none of the rational categories could even apply in a realm
beyond
the phenomenal. Man has rationality to do the work of universalizing
and
that is all.
Finally, Schaeffer seems to be
unfamiliar
with the philosophic roots of the Anglo-Canadian-American tradition.
The
philosopher William Barrett (Irrational Man) has stated that
philosophers
cannot respond to what their own cultural milieu has yet to
live
through. Europe was traumatized by two world wars in a way that America
was not. Correspondingly, Europe's art and philosophy was also shaken
and
does indeed reflect a monumental change in values. It would be a great
mistake and overly simplistic, however, to say that the same holds true
for America. Moreover, it is not a post-Hegelian-Kierkegaardian despair
that afflicts the American
Weltanschauung. True enough, America's
youth have developed a sort of crackerbarrel existentialism -- but
mostly
a much diluted version developed during the '60s.
What, it seems to me, Schaeffer has not
attended to is what is distinctively American about the present outlook
in the U.S. It has not been, nor is it now, an existentialism --
incipient
or otherwise -- that accounts for our present tradition. Rather, it is
the outcome of a distinctively American philosophical movement, not
European.
It was the pragmatist philosophy and its subsequent influence upon the
philosophy of science and logic that best accounts for the present
state
of mind. What pragmatism and the subsequent movement in analytic-logic
oriented philosophy bequeathed to our American thought-milieu was an
epistemology
of fallibilism -- in fact, an unrestricted fallibilism (there
is
no such thing as incorrigible knowledge because
the-data-is-never-all-in,
or it is always conceivable that the present data have been
misconstrued)
. This was not true of the older positivism. It has been fallibilism,
as
it has utterly permeated the university systems in Canada, Britain and
America, that best accounts for the loss of confidence in absolutes of
any kind. Perhaps, though, it is safe to say that confidence in logic
itself
has been persistent (although there are a variety of 'other logics"
being
studied).
Schaeffer's Logic
This heading is perhaps misleading,
since
it is Schaeffer's tendency to commit non-sequiturs that I want to
discuss.
Many readers of Schaeffer have shared their own frustrations with me on
this count: Schaeffer makes one statement and then says another
statement
follows from it when there is no apparent logical relationship there at
all. In fact, this is the primary difficulty in loaning Schaeffer's
books
out to unsaved friends.
A particularly flagrant example is found in He Is There and He
Is
Not Silent. While agreeing heartily with all that the title stands
for, the book as a whole is very poorly argued. A case in point is
found
on page eight:
The great problem with beginning with the impersonal is to find any
meaning for the particulars.... If we begin with the impersonal, then
how
do any of the particulars that now exist -- including man -- have any
meaning?
Nobody has given us an answer to that. In all the history of
philosophical
thought, whether from the East or West, no one has given us an answer.22
Perhaps this is an elliptical argument
or enthymeme, but as it stands, it just does not make sense.
What
I suspect is going on is that Schaeffer has a gut-feeling that
complexity
and particularity logically require a personal creator. If the
reader's
intuitions match Schaeffer's, perhaps the passage will have some force;
but logically speaking, it is extremely puzzling to see any necessary
connection
between bare particularity and personality. But most importantly, there
is just no logical entailment involved as Schaeffer seems to suppose. I
can very easily imagine a world in which there are particulars without
persons. Although it is empirically unlikely that the universe of
matter-energy
is eternal, there is no logical necessity -- that is to say, conceptual
necessity -- that (a) the universe should not be eternal, nor (b) that
the universe consist in as many particulars as you please, including
man
-- all that without a "personal beginning." Less stringently, it is
surely
conceivable that the universe exist but have no persons.
The problem of rationalism and the
"Christian
two-storeyed house" has already been taken up, so we pass on to our
final
consideration.
Schaeffer and Personhood: the
"Mannishness"
of Man
Perhaps the most frustrating thing about Schaeffer's writings in
general
is the freedom he takes in coining new terms. I do not doubt for a
moment
that he does so for emphasis and clarity. But time and time again it
would
be in the interest of both precision and clarity if the strange terms
did
not arise. Such animals as "true Truth," "modern modern man," "nothing
nothing," and "moral motions" clutter and confuse rather than clarify
--
and perhaps the greatest difficulty is this notion of "the mannishness
of man." What is clear, virtually after a reading of any of Schaeffer's
material, is that man, and more particularly, the bare notion of a
person,
is absolutely critical to the logical development of his primary
thesis:
the significance of, and salvation for, man.
But, more often than not, it appears that Schaeffer depends upon the
intuitions of his listeners or readers, for nowhere does he
offer
a concise characterization of what it means to be a person. Rather, he
characteristically throws up coinages and then says some extraordinary
things about a hoped-for connotativeness of each. This practice seems
to
me quite analogous to the "God-words" he faults modern liberalism for.
If there is content for the word "person," or "man," then let us have a
full discussion of it.
This is an extremely important request to make of Schaeffer, because
secular materials within the philosophy of mind, psychology,
neurophysiology,
and even experimental parapsychology all are zeroing in on the nature
of
man. Within an atmosphere of such an abundance of secular works on the
subject,23 Schaeffer may not safely throw about
"person-words."
To do so is just to beg the most fundamental questions that are being
heavily
scrutinized today.
Consider "the mannishness of man." What
is that? The closest Schaeffer comes to unpacking this expression is
when
he characterizes man as both "noble" and "cruel," as capable of love --
even at first sight! The trouble is, each of these predicates can
equally
characterize animals. Indeed, is there such a thing as Schaeffer
credits
Dante for: loving at first sight?24 And what a lot of
metaphysical
problems could be solved merely by appending "ishness" to each
worrisome
entity! Imagine -- the essence of books would be their "bookishness";
that
of lumps, their "lumpishness"; and perhaps most informative of all,
that
of slugs their "slugishness." What seems clear is that without an
account
of persons other than connotation words, there is just no significant
defense
being brought against the philosopher of mind's program (in cooperation
with allied disciplines) to reduce the human being to just an
extraordinarily
adaptive biochemical organism. As one prominent philosopher, soon to
publish
a book Persons and Minds,25 put it, "persons" are
just
"culturally emergent entities," nothing more, and certainly not natural
entities (beings with essences in their own right). So "ishness" may be
good fare for young and naive audiences, but at the frontier of
philosophy
of mind and neurophysiology it just begs the question. It is
desperately
important that we draw the intellectual scrimmage line at the right
place
in apologetics -- we dare not be oblivious to Satan's contemporary
strategy!
POSTSCRIPT
Schaeffer, for all that we have
considered,
has provoked us to think. Even if his diagnoses miss their targets by a
degree or two, he has still brought us face-to-face with the monumental
task of working for a culturally-deep Christianity. We all, I think,
have
much more yet to learn from his example. And as long as he writes, he
will
stimulate and provoke widespread response. May God firmly establish the
L'Abri work and many others like it! Schaeffer has shown us -- myself
at
any rate -- that orthodoxy is far from being dull, and that -- in the
words
of his former associate Os Guiness -- the Christian need not be the odd
man out. How exciting to "occupy till He comes"!
SCHAEFFER'S BOOKS THROUGH 1979
Escape from Reason (1968)
The God Who is There (1968)
Death in the City (1969)
Pollution & the Death of Man (1970)
The Church at the End of the 20th Century (1970)
The Mark of the Christian (1970)
The Church Before the Watching World (1971)
True Spirituality (1972)
He is There and He is Not Silent (1972)
Basic Bible Studies (1972)
The New Super-Spirituality (1972)
Back to Freedom and Dignity (1972)
Genesis in Space and Time (1972)
Art and the Bible (1973)
No Little People (1974)
Two Contents, Two Realities (1974)
Joshua & the Flow of Biblical History (1975)
No Final Conflict (1975)
Everybody Can Know (1975; with Edith Schaeffer)
How Should We Then Live? (1976)
Whatever Happened to the Human Race?
(1979; with C. Everett Koop)
REFERENCES
1. The God Who Is There and Escape from Reason.
2. For want of better labels, "Evidentialism" and "Presuppositionalism." Later in this paper I hope to show that neither label conveys much useful information.
3. Richard Russell, "Escape from Reason," International Reformed Bulletin 43 (Fall 1970) , 23.
4. It is also Schaeffer's style that occasionally proves to be a liability. There are points where clarity and precision are sacrificed by solecistic, vague and ambiguous terminology. On some critical issues the reader is frustrated by "living room" parlance, even leaving him to wonder whether there is any theoretical depth behind the talk. More footnoting and references would help remedy this.
5. As I am using the terms, an "apologetic" will denote a specific argumentive approach, while "apologetics" has more the connotation of the academic discipline by that name.
6. Bernard Ramm, Varieties of Christian Apologetics (Grand Rapids: Baker, 1961), p. 13.
7. Ibid., p. 14.
8. Ibid.
9. I think one could own a system in Ramm's sense only in philosophically assessing another's apologetic approach. This would be a sort of meta-apologetics, a second-order discourse about apologetics that hinges upon one's theology and Christian philosophy. But apologetics proper is, as Ramm states, "the strategy of setting forth the truthfulness of the Christian faith." A strategy per se must be systematic, but it seems solecistic to say it is also a system.
10. Francis A. Schaeffer, He Is There and He Is Not Silent (Wheaton, IL: Tyndale House, 1972), p. 16.
11. Ibid., p. 33.
12. Cornelius Van Til, The Defense of the Faith (Philadelphia: Presbyterian and Reformed, 1953), p. 103.
13. Alvin Plantinga, The Nature of Necessity (New York: Oxford, 1974), pp. 196-221.
14. George I. Mavrodes, Belief in God: A Study in the Epistemology of Religion (New York: Random House, 1970).
15. Ibid., pp. 40-41.
16. Francis A. Schaeffer, Escape >From Reason (Chicago: InterVarsity, 1968) p. 23.
17. Plantinga, Nature of Necessity, passim.
18. Cornelius Van Til, Survey of Christian Epistemology (Philadelphia: den Dulk Christian Foundation, 1960), p. xi.
19. Cornelius Van Til, A Christian Theory of Knowledge (Grand Rapids: Baker, 1969) , p. 291.
20. Schaeffer, He Is There..., p. 13.
21. Schaeffer, Escape From Reason, p. 33.
22. Schaeffer, He Is There..., pp. 8-9.
23. E.g., D.C. Dennett, Content and Consciousness and Roland Puccetti, Persons.
24. Schaeffer, Escape from Reason, p. 27.
25. Dr. Joseph Margolis, Temple
University.
Produced for IBRI
PO Box 423
Hatfield, PA 19440
Last updated: January
19,
2002